Paperback : HK$492.00
Is legal reasoning rationally persuasive, working within a discernible structure and using recognisable kinds of arguments? Does it belong to rhetoric in this sense, or to the domain of the merely 'rhetorical' in an adversative sense? Is there any reasonable certainty about legal outcomes in dispute-situations? If not, what becomes of the Rule of Law? Neil MacCormick's book tackles these questions in establishing an overall theory of legal reasoning which shows the essential part 'legal syllogism' plays in reasoning aimed at the application of law, while acknowledging that simple deductive reasoning, though always necessary, is very rarely sufficient to justify a decision. There are always problems of relevancy, classification or interpretation in relation to both facts and law. In justifying conclusions about such problems, reasoning has to be universalistic and yet fully sensitive to the particulars of specific cases. How is this possible? Is legal justification at this level consequentialist in character or principled and right-based? Both normative coherence and narrative coherence have a part to play in justification, and in accounting for the validity of arguments by analogy. Looking at such long-discussed subjects as precedent and analogy and the interpretative character of the reasoning involved, Neil MacCormick expands upon his celebrated Legal Reasoning and Legal Theory (OUP 1978 and 1994) and restates his 'institutional theory of law'.
Is legal reasoning rationally persuasive, working within a discernible structure and using recognisable kinds of arguments? Does it belong to rhetoric in this sense, or to the domain of the merely 'rhetorical' in an adversative sense? Is there any reasonable certainty about legal outcomes in dispute-situations? If not, what becomes of the Rule of Law? Neil MacCormick's book tackles these questions in establishing an overall theory of legal reasoning which shows the essential part 'legal syllogism' plays in reasoning aimed at the application of law, while acknowledging that simple deductive reasoning, though always necessary, is very rarely sufficient to justify a decision. There are always problems of relevancy, classification or interpretation in relation to both facts and law. In justifying conclusions about such problems, reasoning has to be universalistic and yet fully sensitive to the particulars of specific cases. How is this possible? Is legal justification at this level consequentialist in character or principled and right-based? Both normative coherence and narrative coherence have a part to play in justification, and in accounting for the validity of arguments by analogy. Looking at such long-discussed subjects as precedent and analogy and the interpretative character of the reasoning involved, Neil MacCormick expands upon his celebrated Legal Reasoning and Legal Theory (OUP 1978 and 1994) and restates his 'institutional theory of law'.
1: Prologue
2: Rhetoric and the Rule of Law
3: The Legal Syllogism
4: Defending Deduction
5: Universalising Deduction
6: Judging by Consequences
7: Being Reasonable
8: Arguing About Interpretation
9: Using Precedents
10: Legal Narratives
11: Principles, Consistency and Coherence
12: Arguing Defeasibly
13: Judging Mistakenly
Leverhulme Personal Research Professor and Regius Professor of
Public Law and the Law of Nature and Nations, the University of
Edinburgh QC honoris causa, England and Wales 1999
Knighthood for services to scholarship in law 2001
Royal Medal for Humanities and Social Sciences, Royal Society of
Edinburgh 2004
1999-2004 he served as Member of the European Parliament
Rhetoric and the Rule of Law is a fine work. It is stimulating: it
makes the reader want to argue and test its tenets. It is too good
to be read only by legal theorists.
*Joe Thomson, Edinburgh Law Review, Vol 13, 2009*
Its erudite elegance means that it will serve as an excellent
introduction to jurisprudence for undergraduates, as well as
providing a major contribution to legal philosophy. MacCormick
reaffirms the dialectic between the universal and the
particular.
*James Lee, University of Birmingham, Jurisprudence*
![]() |
Ask a Question About this Product More... |
![]() |